Professor Stephen Weatherill,
Somerville College Oxford University
On 3 January 2017 Sir Ivan Rogers
resigned as the UK’s Permanent Representative to the EU. He wrote a widely
publicised letter of resignation. Among several incendiary observations
directed at the government’s perceived unpreparedness for negotiations on
Brexit perhaps the most headline-grabbing was:
‘Contrary to
the beliefs of some, free trade does not just happen when it is not thwarted by
authorities: increasing market access to other markets and consumer choice in
our own, depends on the deals, multilateral, plurilateral and bilateral that we
strike, and the terms that we agree’.
The use of a double negative in
the opening salvo is a little clumsy, but the gist is clear. Removing obstacles
created by authorities does not automatically release free trade. More is
needed. Dealmaking is needed. And this, Sir Ivan stings, is contrary to the
beliefs of some. Who are these ‘some’?
David Davis and Boris Johnson,
possibly. Liam Fox, probably.
The International Trade Secretary
delivered a speech
in Manchester on 29 September 2016 in which, having begun with reference to
Adam Smith’s The Wealth of Nations
(1776), he expressed a desire to ‘remake the intellectual and philosophical
case for free trade’. The speech is peppered with praise for free trade. But
Fox never defines what he means by free trade. His speech
to the Conservative Party Conference in Birmingham a week later is equally
barren. The closest he comes to definitional precision in the speech delivered
in Manchester is to observe, citing Adam Smith for the claim that ‘it is a
moral right for people to buy whatever they want from those who sell it to them
the cheapest’, that the idea that ‘governments should restrict the right of
individuals to exchange their hard work for goods and services at an agreed
price in an open market is one of the gravest infringements of personal liberty
I can think of’. And he drew on the repeal of the Corn laws during Victorian
times as a demonstration of the virtuous release of price competition to the
benefit of consumers.
Fox’s vision demands that the
State keep out of private transactions. The free trade which he wishes to
champion is in truth unregulated trade.
But free trade in this form does
not exist. Governments intervene in markets for myriad reasons and in myriad
ways, and they have been doing so for a very long time. In England the composition
of ale and bread has been the subject of regulation for centuries. Consumers
cannot know for sure that the products on offer in the marketplace are
wholesome, so the State intervenes. These are the earliest forms of modern
consumer protection law, and they reflect an understanding that leaving the
market unregulated will cause it to malfunction where the consumer does not
possess adequate information to distinguish between products according to their
quality. Ale and bread then – videogames and i-phones today, which come with
statutory guarantees of quality. In similar vein the nature of the relationship
between employer and employee is not simply a matter of private negotiation:
State regulation supplies a floor of protection according to an assumption
that, without it, the employee is vulnerable to exploitation or unfair
treatment. The relationship between a landlord and a tenant is regulated for
similar reasons. Markets may also malfunction on the supply-side. Competition
law, in its common law form of restraint of trade and more recently in
statutory guise, places restraints on the conduct of traders because of fear
that a market left unregulated may become contaminated by anti-competitive
agreements or the abuse of monopoly power. As Adam Smith himself remarked in The
Wealth of Nations, ‘People of the same trade seldom meet together even for
merriment and diversion, but the conversation ends in a conspiracy against the
public, or in some contrivance to raise prices’.
Markets are neither free-standing
nor inevitably self-correcting. Sometimes they require protection. So markets
are and long have been built on the correcting influence of public regulation.
Of course one might argue for less or for more public regulation of the market,
but to speak of ‘free trade’ in a market as if it operates with no public
regulation is deeply misleading and lacks historical context. For every
perniciously protectionist rule such as the Corn laws there are hundreds of
virtuous measures of consumer, worker or environmental protection which reflect
the limits of the capacity of unregulated markets to address the pressing
social concerns of the time.
This readily translates to the transnational
plane. ‘Free trade’ across State borders cannot possibly entail a process of
private traders arriving in foreign lands and striking deals with local buyers
without regard for local laws. Those traders will be required to comply with
the local rules that govern the operation of markets – rules of consumer
protection, environmental protection, competition law and so on. And those
rules will doubtless be different from those that apply at home: cultural
specificity and historical accident dictate that regulatory diversity between
States is the norm. These are non-tariff barriers to trade. They mean that
trade is not ‘free’.
There are plenty of ways for
States to get together in order to address such impediments to cross-border trade.
In the abstract there are two extremes. One is to decide that regulatory
diversity should be ignored: a product or service that is good enough for one
market should be treated as good enough for another. The other is to replace
that regulatory diversity by introducing rules which apply in common. The first model directs that States may not
exclude products and services even if they fall below their own locally
determined preferences. This therefore involves States relinquishing regulatory
authority, and in effect placing their market under the jurisdiction of a more
lenient regulator in another State. This raises obviously sensitive issues
associated with accountability and control. The second model requires the
creation of a common rule-making body. Here too States relinquish regulatory
authority, but to a new supra-State authority charged with the responsibility
to select the applicable rule. Here too loom – different – issues associated
with accountability and control. But neither model suggests unregulated trade.
Quite the contrary. Public regulation of one kind or another is necessary to
promote an integrated trading space that spans jurisdictions which are marked
by varying patterns of intervention in the market.
In practice models of economic
integration that fall within the two extremes are found. States sometimes
accept that national measures that impede trade shall be subject to some form
of review: they are typically not automatically set aside but nor, in the cause
of economic integration, are they jealously guarded as inviolable expressions
of local autonomy. In this vein the rules of the WTO assert that national
measures that obstruct cross-border trade may be subject to review. The detail
need not detain us: the point of present relevance is that there is no question
of cross-border trade proceeding between private parties without reference to
public regulation. The material scope of the WTO regime is limited and in any
event there is room to justify national measures of regulation even where they
do impede inter-State trade, for example for reasons associated with the
protection of public health.
This is remote from Dr Fox’s superficial model of
‘free trade’. Free trade agreements are recognised under WTO law and they
represent a deeper commitment to realising the productive energy of
cross-border trade. There are myriad versions but the free trade envisaged is
not unregulated trade. Free Trade Agreements aim to achieve a freeing of trade,
but they do not envisage a wholesale ejection of public regulation from the
market. The case of the EU is more complex again. In the EU the extent to which
control is exercised over State regulatory autonomy in so far as it obstructs
inter-State trade goes still deeper than that exercised through the WTO – this
is the entrancing story of Cassis de
Dijon laced by ambiguities such as Keck.
This is the promotion of deregulated trade within the EU but, given the vital
space permitted to States to justify national measures which obstruct
inter-State trade on grounds of health protection and the public interest more
generally, it is certainly not a charter for unregulated trade. Moreover, the
EU possesses important legislative competences which supplement the free
movement rules as a means to open up the internal market. This covers
legislative harmonisation supported by sector-specific rule-making activity in
areas such as social policy and environmental protection. This programme of
common rulemaking is designed to free trade – but not to leave it unregulated.
In fact the EU, when it legislates, acts to regulate trade, according to common
patterns: better, the EU re-regulates trade, in replacement for pre-existing
and diverse State regulation. EU law promotes cross-border private contracting
within the internal market but not on terms that exclude public regulation.
To return to Sir Ivan Rogers– ‘free
trade does not just happen’. In the transnational sphere, there is no free
trade, there is only freed trade and it is regulated trade. The extent to which
it is freed and the terms according to which it is regulated depends on the
deals struck and the enforcement mechanisms created in their support. It
requires transnational negotiation, design of rules and of institutions. It – again
to return to Sir Ivan – ‘depends on the deals, multilateral, plurilateral and
bilateral that we strike, and the terms that we agree’. The people of the UK
have voted to quit the EU and that will lead also to the UK falling out of the scope
of the EU’s several dozen free trade agreements with third countries. That will
not grant the UK free trade. It will diminish the UK’s enjoyment of freed
trade. And it will demand that the UK does a great deal of dealmaking even to
begin to replace what it has lost. In Victorian times, to which Dr Fox pays
much wistful attention in his Manchester speech, the UK’s economic and
political strength allowed it to swagger its way to oceans of beneficial
trading activity. The balances of power are different today. It is not
conceivable that post-Brexit the UK will get anything other than a worse deal with
the EU-27 than it enjoys currently, given that the percentage of total export
trade which the UK does with the EU-27 is so many times higher than that which
the EU-27 does with the UK. The UK needs the EU a great deal more than the EU
needs the UK. And equally it is not conceivable that post-Brexit the UK will
get anything other than a worse deal than it enjoys currently with trading
partners elsewhere in the world, given that the UK, population 64 million, has
so much less clout and so much less to offer than the EU-27, population 440
million.
Trade today cannot be effectively
promoted by unilateral action. Dealmaking is required. And that requires
concessions. As the House of Lords European Union Committee felicitously put it
in its December 2016 report
on Brexit: the Options for Trade, ‘there
is always an inherent trade-off between liberalising trade and the exercise of
sovereignty’ (page 3). It adds that as a general rule ‘the deeper trade
relationship, the greater the loss of sovereignty’ (page 76). I would treat ‘sovereignty’
with as much suspicion as I treat ‘free trade’: as a label, it is at best
unhelpfully imprecise, at worst an anachronism. Better to frame the discussion
in terms of power in practice as distinct from power in principle. In the
current conditions of interdependence among States in Europe the State that
insists on exercising its power unilaterally may pride itself on its adherence
to principle but it will find that in practice its ability to address problems
that spill over borders – climate change, migration, trade, and so on – is
seriously diminished. It needs to co-operate with other States to find
solutions. That co-operation extends its power in practice. All States gain from
agreeing to be locked into a mutually agreed framework for addressing problems:
each gives up a degree of autonomy in principle but in return knows that all
other participants have made precisely the same concession.
Voting rules are vividly
emblematic of the trade-offs at stake. A rule of unanimity preserves a veto but
it is one that is held by all members of the bloc, so that difficult decisions
are unlikely to be taken: this is to privilege ‘sovereignty’ in principle over the
facilitation of practical dealmaking. Embrace of majority voting acquiesces in
the possibility of being outvoted in return for a power also to outvote: deals
will be struck more readily, though on occasion under sufferance. Voting rules
are one of the design choices that have to be made by co-operating States. So engaging
in multilateral trade deals typically involves some degree of self-restraint
measured in commitments to comply with binding norms located at the
transnational level – promises not to obstruct trade (typically except in
defined circumstances), promises to apply rules agreed in common. This is to
yield power (to act unilaterally) in principle yet it enhances power in
practice. ‘Free trade’ is really about regulated trade – negotiating the terms
of ‘free trade’ is really about negotiating the patterns of regulation that
will provide the foundation for trade.
This is ‘free trade’ in a modern
world of densely regulated markets and unavoidably interdependent States. It is
an agenda of multilateralism. To suppose that free trade simply happens when
governments get out of the way is an exercise in evading complexity.
Seen from the outside one has the
increasing impression that those who drove the people of the UK to vote for Brexit
and who are now in charge of plotting the future do not even understand the
first thing about what ‘free trade’ means today, in the EU or more generally.
Sir Ivan’s comments suggest that that is what it looks like from the inside
too.
Barnard
& Peers, European Union Law:
chapter 27, chapter 11
Photo: Adam Smith
Photo credit: Adam Smith Institute, www.adamsmith.org
Surely 'free' trade works in the same way as other markets: buyers and sellers have more choice in counter-parties. Modern supply chains and information flows have dramatically reduced the transactional costs of any individual exchange and the costs of managing product and service delivery. Of course, reducing these costs mean that more transactions are 'bought'. It would be interesting to model the impact of changing the costs of these transactions on overall industries.
ReplyDeleteIndeed, it could be considered negligent not to estimate such impacts before starting on any journey that could increase the transactional costs.
And as with any exchange, there is a degree of government intervention to protect consumers, creditors, et al, and also (because the products or services cross a border) because of broader economic and non-economic welfare concerns.
DeleteI think Sir Ivan is wrong, no I also have to disagree with my academic colleagues. Free trade has two distinct meanings. The first is non-discrimination (mainly national treatment but additionally most favoured nation). This requires prohibitions on government action; and that is all. The second meaning is deregulation. There is no such thing, in practice, as an entirely deregulated market but that is not because this is legally or conceptually impossible. It is because we prioritise other values over unregulated trade, e.g. Environment, consumer safety, etc. Some regulation also helps trade (e.g. harmonisation, equivalence) but it is also not necessary. So on neither definition is regulation an element of free trade. At most, competition law but even that can be run as nondiscrimination.
ReplyDeleteThanks, Lorand. I think the point is that if 'free trade' in the form of lack of regulation is sold as a politically realistic objective that is not honest - because any trade liberalisation will be accompanied in practice by some form of residual regulation, and/or even (as you say) some form of regulation to facilitate that liberalisation.
Delete