Anna Dannreuther; all views are the author's own
In its judgment yesterday in International
Stem Cell Corporation on biotechnology patents, the CJEU qualified its
ruling in Brüstle
by shifting the emphasis of what it takes for a non-fertilised human ovum
stimulated by parthenogenesis to constitute a ‘human embryo’ and thus be
unpatentable under the Biotechnology Directive. The Court ruled that in order
to constitute a ‘human embryo’ for the purposes of the Directive, the stimulated
ovum must have the ‘inherent capacity to develop into a human being’. This is in
contrast to its previous ruling in Brüstle
where it held that such an ovum would only constitute a ‘human embryo’ if it
were ‘capable of commencing the
process of development of a human being’.
Background
The case concerns the patentability of living material under the Biotechnology
Directive 98/44. The aim of the
Directive is to strike a balance between encouraging biotechnological research by
way of patent law and protecting the dignity and integrity of the person. As
such, while the Directive treats biotechnological inventions generally no
differently from any other inventive science that comes forward with patent
claims, it forbids patenting certain processes on ethical grounds. In addition
to a general prohibition on inventions whose patentability would go against
public order or morality, it specifically forbids patenting the following
processes: cloning human beings, modifying the germ line of humans, and using
human embryos for industrial or commercial purposes.
In the 2011 judgment in Brüstle, the
CJEU had the opportunity to define ‘human embryo’. This was in the context of a
German neurobiologist who held a patent in Germany for the production of neural
precursor cells from human embryonic stem cells (confusingly, this term is used
even when they are not stem cells derived from human embryos). He claimed his
methods offered promising methods of treatment for neurological diseases. Greenpeace
challenged the validity of the patent on the ground that the process involved
using human embryos. The referring court asked the CJEU several questions
relating to the nature of the concept ‘human embryo’ under the Directive. The
Court held that:
any
human ovum after fertilisation… and any non-fertilised human ovum whose
division and further developments have been stimulated by parthenogenesis
constitute a ‘human embryo’. [para 38]
The Court justified the unpatentability of both fertilised ova and
non-fertilised ova on the basis that the latter were, just like embryos created
by fertilisation of an ovum, ‘capable of commencing
the process of development of a human being’ [para 36].
In the present case, International Stem Cell Corporation seeks to
register as a patent in the UK the process of ‘parthenogenetic activation of
oocytes for the production of human embryonic stem cells’ (for ease, I will
refer to the activated oocytes (ova) as ‘parthenotes’). Essentially, the
process involves ‘activating’ a human ovum by a variety of chemical and
electrical techniques. Such an activated ovum can develop into the blastocyst
phase (about 200-300 cells following cell division) but it is unable to develop
further, as it lacks the paternal DNA necessary to form extra-embryonic
material (placenta). The process falls
into the third category of processes which Brüstle
deemed unpatentable by virtue of constituting a ‘human embryo’.
Henry Carr QC, sitting as Deputy Judge of the High Court, queried
whether the Court’s interpretation in Brüstle
can be correct if, in light of current scientific knowledge, parthenotes are
incapable of developing into a human being. He decided to refer a question to
the CJEU on the point. In his judgment, he strongly suggested that the Court
should rule in favour of excluding this particular process from the notion of
‘human embryo’. At paragraph 35 he observes:
Stem cells have the potential to revolutionise
the treatment of human disease because of their capacity to differentiate into
almost any type of adult cell. The recitals to the Biotech Directive express
two competing policy considerations. On the one hand, the research in the field
of biotechnology is to be encouraged by means of the patent system, and on the
other hand, that patent law must be applied so as to respect the fundamental
principles safeguarding the dignity and integrity of the person…The Biotech
Directive is to be interpreted in a way that balances these competing policy
considerations.
Judgment
The Court states that the principle in Brüstle must be taken to mean that in
order to be classified as a ‘human embryo’, an unfertilised human ovum whose
division and further development have been stimulated by parthenogenesis (a
parthenote) must necessarily have the ‘inherent capacity of developing into a
human being’ [para 28]. Endorsing the Advocate General’s Opinion, the Court
thus stresses that the emphasis is on whether the parthenote can develop into a human being, rather than
whether it can commence this process.
The determination of whether a parthenote has such a capacity is left for the
national courts to determine [para 36 – 38].
The Court does not explain its reasoning for
the change in emphasis. It does acknowledge a divergence of scientific
information in the written observations before the court in the present case
and in Brüstle. Whereas in the
present case the information provided suggested that parthenotes could not
develop into human beings, the information in Brüstle suggested that parthenotes could develop into human beings
[paras. 31. 33]. This seems to be one of the ‘foregoing considerations’
mentioned in paragraph 38 that the Court bases its judgment on. The Court did
not deal with the eventuality that the parthenote could be genetically
manipulated in such a way that it can develop to term as International Stem
Cell Corporation had amended their applications for registration to exclude the
prospect of additional genetic information.
Comments
The Court’s decision is to be welcomed. It qualifies Brüstle so that parthenotes are not
automatically included in the definition of ‘human embryo’ and hence excluded
from patenting. It thus allows for the patenting of biological research
involving alternative methods of obtaining embryonic stem cells. However, two
points of contention should be noted.
First, as the Advocate General point outs in paragraph 43 of his Opinion,
Member States are still able to prohibit patentability of parthenotes under Article
6(1) of the Directive on the grounds of public order or morality. Although the
shift from outright exclusion to determination by Member States will be
welcomed by more biologically protective States (such as Poland, who intervened
in the case to argue for parthenotes’ exclusion from patentability in the
interests of safeguarding human dignity) there are risks in this. As the
patentability of parthenotes is now dependent solely on Member States’ cultural
norms, a ‘patent tourism’ could emerge, whereby parthenote stem cell
researchers will locate in jurisdictions which welcome their processes and
avoid those which do not. Given the economic disadvantages for parthenote
researchers locating in unwelcoming patent jurisdictions, this may not bear
well on freedom of establishment and free movement of services. Although this
is a potential risk for all biotechnological processes, the shifting classification
of parthenotes may lead to greater divergence in their treatment across Member
States.
Second, the judgment lacks any kind of discussion on at what point the
organism develops into a human being and is thus excluded from the concept of
‘human embryo’. The Court leaves it to the national court to determine whether
the parthenote has the ‘inherent capacity to develop into a human being’. This
is unhelpful as the national court has to decide both whether the parthenote
has the inherent capacity to develop into a human being, and if not, whether it
is prohibited from being patented on grounds of morality and/or public order. This
seems like a lot to labour national courts with, who could have done with some
guidance on the principle. Equally, the principles to be deduced from the cases
are tricky. Seeing as Brüstle still
maintains that fertilised human ova constitute ‘human embryos’, are national
courts to assume that parthenotes do not constitute human beings to the extent
that they fail to make extra-embryonic tissue and therefore differ from
fertilised human ova? What if parthenotes were created which could make extra-embryonic tissue? Would
the case law suggest that these parthenotes could lead to the development of a
human being? Even if this seems simple or obvious, it would have been useful
for the Court to clarify this.
Equally, a comment on the patentability of parthenotes, which could then
be subject to later genetic manipulation, would have been useful.
Conclusion
As
it stands, patenting parthenotes is no longer definitively prohibited due to
their classification as ‘human embryos’ under Brüstle. However, their patentability is determined wholly by
Member States, either on the grounds of public order or morality, or whether
the Member State classifies them as ‘human embryos’ under the new definition. The
judgment would have been more helpful if it had given guidance to national
courts on what constitutes ‘development into a human being’.
Photo credit: Daily Telegraph
This comment has been removed by a blog administrator.
ReplyDeleteThis comment has been removed by a blog administrator.
ReplyDelete