The
Islamic headscarf issue has finally reached the Court of Justice of the
European Union (CJEU) through two preliminary references, Achbita and Bougnaoui, issued
by Belgian and French courts, respectively. While the CJEU has –directly or
indirectly– dealt with religious freedom issues before in the context of the
internal market (see eg Van
Duyn v Home Office) or the right to asylum (see Bundesrepublik
Deutschland v Y and Z), this is the first time that the CJEU
has ever been asked about religious discrimination under Directive
2000/78 (the 'employment equality' Directive), although
the latter prohibits religious discrimination in employment within the EU since
2000. In addition, these are the first two cases where the CJEU is confronted
with the issue of whether restricting the use of the Islamic headscarf at work
can amount to religious discrimination. In contrast, several national
jurisdictions* and the European Court of
Human Rights (ECtHR) (see eg Ebrahimian
v France) have already dealt with this matter.
This
thus is an excellent opportunity for the CJEU to position itself as regards the
ECtHR’s case law on religious dress and to clarify how the employment equality Directive should be interpreted
in religious discrimination instances. Indeed, both cases have been assigned to
the Grand Chamber, which signposts their potential importance, and the hearings
are scheduled for today.
Background of the disputes
These
two cases have some common features: the applicants are Muslims working for
private companies; they both used to wear the hijab (ie the Islamic veil that
covers the head and the chest, but not the face) at work; and, in both
cases, their employer considered that this was in conflict with the respective
organisations’ neutrality policy, so after refusing to remove the hijab at
work, the applicants were dismissed. Bougnaoui and Achbita should
thus be distinguished from the ECtHR case SAS v
France (see a commentary here),
which concerned the French ban to wear the burqa and the niqab (ie the Islamic
veils that cover the full body, including the face) in public spaces (and
not within a private company, as it was the case in Bougnaoui and
Achbita).
On the
other hand, however, there are also some differences between these two cases.
Firstly, Bougnaoui was wearing the headscarf from the outset, that is, from the
very first day she was working for the employer (Micropole Univers). In
contrast, Achbita only decided to start wearing it during working hours
after being in employment for three years with the company ‘G4S Secure
Solutions’ (she nevertheless always wore it outside work). Secondly, Bougnaoui
worked as an engineer who spent some of her working time at Micropole Univers’
premises, and some other time working at clients’ premises. The company’s
position was that she should not wear the hijab when she had to be in contact
with clients (either at the company’s own premises or at the clients’ offices),
but she was allowed to wear the hijab the rest of the time. Conversely,
Achbita, who worked as a receptionist, was not allowed to wear the headscarf at
all. Finally, while in Bougnaoui there was an express complaint of a
client who was ‘inconvenienced’ by the hijab and requested that she did not
wear it the next time, according to the information publicly available, in the Achbita
case there was not an explicit client complaint.
The
questions asked by the referring courts are also different. In Achbita,
the Belgian court asks whether the employer’s neutrality rule amounts to direct
discrimination, while in Bougnaoui, the French court asks whether the
neutrality requirement can amount to an occupational requirement (art 4(1), employment equality Directive) if
it is a client’s demand. In my view,
however, the central issue at stake in both claims is whether an employer’s
duty to accommodate religious practices can be derived from the EU concept of
indirect discrimination (art 2(2)(b), employment
equality Directive).
The questions asked by the national courts
Direct or indirect discrimination?
Neutrality
rules are normally classical examples of the type of policies that can amount
to indirect discrimination. Typically, they are not introduced because
some employees profess a given faith, but rather to preserve the organisation’s
image or the principle of secularism. So they usually are neutral on their face
and they apply to everyone, but in practice they can put at disadvantage
certain groups, eg people who feel compelled to express their religious
believes through certain religious practices or dresses. Indeed, in this case,
both claimants were arguably put at disadvantage by the neutrality policies,
and so would have been anyone trying to wear a religious symbol or dress in
their respective workplaces. It thus seems relatively straightforward that
these neutrality policies can amount to indirect discrimination.
However,
there may be instances where a particular policy or practice can amount to
either direct or indirect discrimination depending on the specific factual
circumstances surrounding the case. As the CJEU has recently noted, the key
element to differentiate between direct and indirect discrimination is that:
‘[i]f it is apparent that a measure which gives rise to a difference in
treatment has been introduced for reasons relating to [the protected
characteristic], that measure must be classified as ‘direct
discrimination’ within the meaning of [EU law]. By contrast, indirect
discrimination […] does not require the measure at issue to be based on reasons
of that type. […] It is sufficient that, although using neutral criteria not
based on the protected characteristic, it has the effect of placing
particularly persons possessing that characteristic at a disadvantage’ (CHEZ
Razpredelenie Bulgaria AD, paras 95-96).
The
information publicly available on the Achbita case suggests that the
company’s neutrality policy existed before she started wearing the headscarf at
work. However, it seems that after the conflict with the claimant arose, and ‘[f]aced
with the persistence of the employee to wear the headscarf during working hours,
the company’s board of directors decided to amend work regulations in order to
forbid the workers to wear any visible symbol expressing their political,
philosophical or religious beliefs’.** This
suggests that there might be a causal link between the employer’s decision to
ban wearing visible religious symbols and Achbita’s decision to start wearing
the hijab at work. While this is a matter of proof to be considered by the
national court, if there is enough evidence to suggest that this prohibition
was introduced because of the religious conflict that arose between
Achbita and the company, it could arguably amount to direct
discrimination.
Can a client’s ‘neutrality requirement’ amount
to an occupational requirement?
Whether
the policies at stake in these two cases amount to direct or indirect
discrimination, at the justification stage, the employers could try to rely on
article 4(1) of the employment equality
Directive to argue that not wearing the headscarf at work is an occupational
requirement, in other words, that it is genuinely necessary ‘by reason of the
nature’ of the job ‘or the context in which [it is] carried out’, and that
requiring this is legitimate and proportionate. However, it seems that this
argument was only put forward in Bougnaoui.
The
fact that in that case a client requested that in the future the claimant did
not wear the hijab resonates with the Firma
Feryn case, where a Belgian company director publicly stated
that he was not willing to hire Moroccans because he had to comply with its
‘customers requirements’, who did not want domestic alarm systems being
installed by ‘immigrants’ (AG
Poiares Maduro’ Opinion in Firma Feryn, para 4). In that
case, AG Poiares Maduro concluded that not hiring Moroccans for that reason
amounted to direct discrimination –which was confirmed by the Court– and he
noted that the fact that customers were ‘unfavourably disposed towards
employees of a certain ethnic origin’ simply ‘illustrate[d] that “markets will
not cure discrimination” and that regulatory intervention is essential’ (paras 18-19 of the opinion).
In Bougnaoui,
not wearing a headscarf was not genuinely necessary and determining to
successfully perform the substance of the applicant’s job as an
engineer. Furthermore, the occupational requirement exception is only
applicable to ‘very limited situations’ (recital
23, employment equality Directive) and exceptions to the
principle of equal treatment should be interpreted strictly (Prigge v Lufthansa, paras 56, 71). Therefore, the client’s
request that Bougnaoui should not wear the headscarf should not be interpreted
as an acceptable occupational requirement, as
defined in article 4(1) of the employment equality Directive.
Although the employer could also try to rely on article 2(5) of the Directive
to justify this policy arguing that it was necessary to protect the rights and
freedoms of others, the mere fact that the client did not like watching
the applicant wearing the headscarf does not seem a legitimate reason to
claim that third parties’ ‘rights and freedoms’ were affected.
The key underlying issue: can a duty to
accommodate religious practices be derived from the EU concept of indirect
discrimination?
Under
EU law, the employer has a duty to reasonably accommodate disabled persons (art 5, employment equality Directive), and
to some extent pregnant women (Directive 92/85/EEC, art 5(1)). While EU law does not
formally recognise this duty for any other ground, some academics argue that it
could be derived from the concept of indirect
discrimination,*** as it has been the case
in Canada (Ontario Human Rights Commission (O’Malley) v
Simpsons-Sears [1985] 2 SCR
536). This could be especially suitable for
cases where religious practices clash with the protection of a legitimate
objective or with the protection of the rights and freedoms of others.
Indeed,
while the ECtHR has not explicitly recognised a duty of reasonable
accommodation for religious believes, in Thlimmenos it stated that:
The
right not to be discriminated against in the enjoyment of the rights guaranteed
under the Convention is also violated when States without an objective and
reasonable justification fail to treat differently persons whose situations are
significantly different. (Thlimmenos v Greece, para 44)
This
effectively means that states should accommodate persons who have different
needs unless there is an ‘objective and reasonable justification’ not do it. In
other words, the ECtHR suggests that the ‘reasonableness’ of accommodation
should be analysed as part of the objective justification test which is
inherent to indirect discrimination and entails considering whether the failure
to treat the claimant differently pursues a legitimate aim and is
proportionate.
The
ECtHR has been reluctant to apply this principle in religious discrimination
cases in the education sector (see
eg Dahlab v Swistzeland; Sahin v Turkey; Dogru v France) and in
the public sector (see eg X v UK, Kosteski v Former Yugoslavia Republic of
Macedonia, Ebrahimian v France). However, when the ‘accommodation conflict’
arises outside an educational environment and between private parties (ie when there
is no need to preserve state’s neutrality), the ECtHR seems to put a lower
threshold to find that the rule at stake is not justified, and thus, the
religious practice should be accommodated. That was the case in Eweida v UK , where –like in Bougnaoui
and Achbita– the religious accommodation conflict arose within a private
company.
Within
the EU, the CJEU has outlined the principle of equal treatment as requiring not
only that identical situations are treated in the same manner, but also that
different situations are treated differently (see eg Joint Cases T-18/89 and 24/89, Tagaras; Case T-10/93, A v Commission), which echoes the ‘reasonable and
objective justification’ requirement recognised by the ECtHR in Thlimmenos.
Accordingly, the same reasoning could be followed by the CJEU in a case
concerning a religious accommodation conflict. In fact, in Prais the CJEU already accepted
that the accommodation of religious believes was ‘desirable’, although not
required on the facts. Prais was a Jewish applicant to an EU civil service
competition. She asked for the date to be changed because it coincided with a
Jewish holiday that forbids travelling and writing. When her request was
rejected, she argued that it amounted to a violation of the Staff Regulations,
which established that candidates should be selected without distinction on
grounds of religion. The Court recognised that the appointing authority ‘should
[…] endeavour to avoid such [religious] dates’, but because she had not informed
the Council before fixing the date, the Council was not obliged to accommodate
Prais’ believes (paras 16-18).
Against
this framework, and given the parallel between the ECtHR and the CJEU’s
definitions of equal treatment, it could be expected that in Bougnaoui
and Achbita the latter will follow the approach of the ECtHR in Thlimmenos
and Eweida to recognise –at least tacitly– that a duty to reasonably
accommodate religious differences can be derived from the concept of indirect
discrimination. It will be interesting to see whether the Grand Chamber takes this route or it follows a
different approach to address this issue.
Photo credit: Mizrahilaw.com
Barnard & Peers: chapter 9, chapter 20
* See eg the Danish case Føtex,
22/2004 No.U.2005.1265.H (Supreme Court, 21 January 2005); the UK case Azmi
v Kirklees MBC [2007] ICR 1154 (EAT); the Belgian case Hema (Tongres
Labour Court, 2 January 2013) and the French case Association Baby Lou,
decision No S 13/02981 (Court of Appeal of Paris, 27 October 2013).
** E Bribosia, ‘The preservation of the
neutral image of a private company may justify the dismissal of employees wearing
the headscarf’, European network of legal experts in the non-discrimination
field (11 January 2012),
citing the Judgment in case G4S, A.R. 2010/AA/453 en 2010/AA/467 (Antwerp
Labour Court of Appeal, 23 December 2011).
*** L Waddington, ‘Reasonable
Accommodation’ (2011) 36 NTM/NJCM-Bulletin 41, 49; K Alidadi, ‘Reasonable
accommodation for religion and belief: adding value to art. 9 ECHR and the EU’s
anti-discrimination approach in employment?’ (2012) 37 ELRev 693,
707-710; S Benedi Lahuerta, ‘Taking EU Equality Law to the Next Level: in
Search of Coherence’ (2016) European Labour Law Journal (forthcoming).
Things will be better in the future inshallah...
ReplyDeleteIslamic women who choose to wear the hijab it allows them to retain their modesty, morals and freedom of choice. They choose to cover because they believe it is liberating and allows them to avoid harassment. Islam promotes modest dress among women. Many Muslim women wear a headscarf, often known as a hijab and in Quranic Arabic as the khimar. Many of these garments cover the hair, ears and throat, but do not cover the face. Why Wear Hijab
ReplyDelete